All posts by Henry Xia

Heraclitus: death is a blur

A mysterious Persian philosopher in 500 BCE (the same region was latter inhabited by Greeks). Heraclitus is mysterious because not too much informations have been recorded about his life, most of his stories were only retailed based on the inferences of his personal feature throughout his master pieces. Heraclitus is one of the “pre-socratics” philosophers, the formation of his theory have been considered highly related to several first (philosophy) thinkers in his region. These philosophers include Thales, Anaximander and Anaximenes. Heraclitus and other pre-socratics thinkers significantly marked “the birth of natural philosophy”(Garvey 25). Heraclitus was commonly known from his theory the “universal flux”, that every thing are constantly changing over time. An illustration of this idea is his famous metaphor of the changing stream. “Heraclitus, I believe, says that all things pass and nothing stays, and comparing existing things to the flow of a river, he says you could not step twice into the same river”(Plato Cratylus 402a = A6). Heraclitus also puts forward such fundamental view of world’s pattern by raising “the unity of opposites”. Every pairs of opposites are meaningless without one another, thus could be seen as a unity. He also provides a method to understanding the world’s formation based on cosmology. “This world-order, the same of all, no god nor man did create, but it ever was and is and will be: everliving fire, kindling in measures and being quenched in measures” (B 30). Heraclitus believes that fire is the essential substance; since his world view was most likely attributed to the notion that a world would both reborn and terminate by fire. 

Based on previous studies, Heraclitus’s “cosmos fire” theory is an analogy of the soul, that expressed his view of death. Concretely, there is a combination of his three theories. With the unity of opposites, he primarily represents a state of existed entities, that every things and their opposites are strongly bonded together; hence, an abstraction of an eternal circulation. The opposite of a kindled fire is being quenched, yet these are the only states the fire would possess. In addition, one assumption that Heraclitus made to support the existence of such circulation, is the universal flux. The principle that every thing constantly changing serves as a “scope” to the opposite’s circulation, in terms of a basic manifestation of the physical world’s state. Only the fire’s kindle-quench process is persistently changing, the opposites would remain as a unity. 

“As the same thing in us are living and dead, waking and sleeping, young and old. For these things having changed around are those, and those in turn having changed around are these”.(B88)

An essential assumption is, death and alive are two opposite states. Yet under the same mechanism represented in the cosmos fire theory, the “individual’s soul fire” (Hussy 1)  also alternates between quenching and kindling. Nevertheless, the combined view of Heraclitus’s theories seems limited due to the strict assumptions. Through out his fragments, one would treat him as a highly systematic theorist. Fire plays a central role in both his view of cosmos and soul, and each being a pattern of “unity-in-opposite”(Hussey 1). He reckons a general order of the universe by imposes the cosmos fire’s example. Thus, it is complicated to understand the universe is ever living, since it is twinkling between living and dying. The same conclusion also stands in terms of souls. In addition, several “unity of oppositions” propounded by Heraclitus as examples of his doctrines, have crucial influences.  According to Heraclitus, the opposition of life-death is linked with mortal-immortal, and human-divine.His proposition of death, is then denote to a fragment of a process other than a termination. 

As one of the pre-socratics thinkers, Heraclitus has been delineated as immortal. An example in this case, is “The Battle of Gods and Giants”, a symbolism of a historical events happened in Heraclitus’s era. The sanctification of this story suggest that there is a “difficulty of saying anything definitive about the lives of the earliest Greek philosophers” (Garvey 25). Therefore, the unknown informations of Heraclitus’s death was to some extent echoed with his world view. Such world view, to some extent considered the consequence of death in a same way as Buddhism. Specifically, the buddhism doctrine indicates that every being in this world have a soul, and each would reincarnation into another being after death. The belief of samsara therefore  based on a core assumption of buddhism, which called hetu-phala. It then explains why should individual’s pursuing for virtue. Yet the reason is, the good deeds in this life, would transform into the welfare in next life. The similar mechanism about death revealed in Heraclitus’s world view, one inquiry is, how would Heraclitus responds to the hetu-phala. 

Work Cited Page

Garvey, James, and Jeremy Stangroom. “The Story of Philosophy: A History of Western Thought.” The Story of Philosophy: A History of Western Thought. London: Quercus, 2013. 25-38. Print.

Kirk, G. S. “Heraclitus and Death in Battle (FR. 24D).” The American Journal of Philology 70.4 (1949): 384. Print.

Hussey, Edward. “Heraclitus on Living and Dying.” Monist 74.4 (1991): 517-30. Print.

Graham, Daniel W. “Heraclitus.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University, 03 Sept. 2019. Web. 25 June 2021.

Albert Camus: Dying or being Absurd

A 20th-century thinker with mixed identities. He was a journalist, political activist, play writer ,and director. Although he does not treat himself as a philosopher, his voices seem to prefer the rationalism approach. Camus is unique among the other continental thinkers; he denies most of the theoretical approaches’ significance. Yet, most of his ideas were expressed through metaphors and political practices. Several of his works have profoundly reflects his assertion of death, including The Stranger, La Mort Heureuse, reflections on Guillotine. Concretely, Camus revealed a triangle relationship between fate, absurdity, and happiness. Although there are various purposes of these works, Camus used metaphors and story constructions to symbolize these ideas. 

  Camus’s life has thoroughly been covered from World War I to the ending of World War II to address his early life. He was born in November 1913, which is only one year before the war started. Yet his father died in the war before Camus was one year old. Since his mother later found a housekeeper job in (French) Algeria, he followed his mother, and the elder brother moved there. Camus has struggled in arduousness for most of his life. Consequently, such context has a significant impact on his worldview. Although Camus has persuasively denied himself of being an existentialist, his proposition of death’s meaning has strongly indicated an “anti-philosophical approach,” which he applied to oppose existentialism inquiry.  

At the opening of the Myth of Sisyphus, Camus puts “There is but one severe philosophical problem, and that is suicide.” By “suicide,” he actually means “suicide to resist the distant external world.” Eventually, his answer to this question is “no.” Simultaneously, as Camus was writing this philosophical essay which was intended to express the idea of absurdity, Camus was also suffering tuberculosis, and his country was facing the war (Kaplan 92). Therefore, although Camus behold absurdity abounds in one’s life, he tries to manage its force in terms of a positive expectation for living. According to the Greek myth, Sisyphus was punished to roll a heavy rock to the top of a mountain and roll it back to the bottom of the hill, which is endless and hopeless. Happiness, as Camus suggests, is such a process of fighting against the absurdity of life while awarding it is permanent and irreparable. “Since existence itself has no meaning, we must learn to bear an irresolvable emptiness” (Aronson). 

With the message that life is absurd in a variety of ways, the meaning of death also penetrates through Camus’s The Stranger; “Camus believed that aside from the limitations of view and the absurdity of life, human could make a decision to get away from misery” (Salsabila and Tjahjani 2). The protagonist in The Stranger Meursault is an affectless person and has a serene lifestyle, as Camus illustrated. He is a person that did not show any sorrow while his mother passed away. Under his friend Raymond’s instigation, he bloodily killed two Arabs while he and Raymond spent their holiday. There are some typical interactions between Meursault and “the sense of death.” When Meursault asked Raymond for a gun initially, despite his safekeeping thought, he perversely perceived a desire of murdering. Therefore, contradictive protagonist’s portraits occur before and after the climax, which is the conflict between them and the Arabs. He eventually felt both the faintness of the anticipation of death and the absurdity of his life. The transformation of one’s sense of fate is thus rapidly occurred, as Camus described. If we then explain his triangle relationship theory, one’s aspiration of death is actually self-determined by the absurdity in one’s life. Whereas happiness, as Camus described, is our discoveries of passions that overcame life’s absurdness. For instance, while Meursault was facing the death penalty, he starts to imagine his future with his girlfriend and how they get married. As he puts it in La Mort Heureuse (Camus’s maiden work)“Happiness and absurd are the two sons of the same earth” (Camus 122).

Additionally, In his other work, The Reflection On Guillotine, Camus also revealed his assertion that government should ban the death penalty by persuading the reason death is not as intimidating as the restraint of the other humanitarian passions. “For capital punishment to be really intimidating, human nature would have to be different; it would have to be as stable and serene as the law itself. But then human nature would be dead” (Camus 9). Although the original purpose of this essay is to fulfill his political assertion, and the application of the “passion argument” is also under another context, Camus revealed the same phase of death and absurdity’s relationship. One’s understanding and contemplation of death would only lead by the extent that one wants to defeat absurdity or how much one enjoyed in one’s life. The magnitude of murders and criminals has not been reduced under death penalties since human nature majorly consists of freewill, lust, and chaos. From Camus’s potion of view, these so-called “passions” are far more desirable than maintaining a tedious and absurd life. Consequently, individuals would more likely exchange such life with their liberties. Yet Camus also seems to contradict himself in-between the dilemma of whether passions would lead to happiness or impulses. 

In an overview of Camus’s words of death, he uncovered that the nature of death is desirable since we always derived from the absurdity of this world and tried to defeat it by putting ourselves near an end. While he also suggests there is another route of dealing with nonsense, which is to maintain our lives by passions, it could cause negative consequences from the legal system’s perspective. Camus’s life ends in a car accident in 1960. He was on the trip returning to Paris after the vacation. Based on police records back then, Camus’s vehicle didn’t speeding. The road surface and the landform were just as usual.

Nevertheless, the vehicle served to a tree, immediately killed Camus. Camus witnessed the absurdity of this world undergo his own life. Although his literary career successfully ended World War II, even his death comes absurdly. None can anticipate whether Camus was still eager his wild life before the accident took his life, but he reimagined the significance of death in terms of one’s determinant of fate. 

Work cited page 

Baker, Carlos. “A Happy Death: By Albert Camus, Translated by Richard Howard New York, Alfred A. Knopf, 1972. 192 Pp. $5.95.” Theology Today 29.4 (1973): 444-45. Print.

Salsabila, Indiana, and Joesana Tjahjani. “Absurdity and The Significance of the Idea of Death in Albert Camus’ L’Étranger.” Proceedings of the Proceedings of the 1st Conference of Visual Art, Design, and Social Humanities by Faculty of Art and Design, CONVASH 2019, 2 November 2019, Surakarta, Central Java, Indonesia (2020). Print.

Kaplan, Alice. “Looking for “The Stranger”.” (2016). Print.

Scherr, Arthur. “Camus and the Denial of Death: Meursault and Caligula.” OMEGA – Journal of Death and Dying 69.2 (2014): 169-90. Print.

Camus, Albert. “Réflexions Sur La Guillotine.” (2010). Print.

Marrouchi, Mustapha. “Stirrings Still; Or, The Impossibility of Mourning the Deaths of Edward Said.” College Literature 31.1 (2004): 201-14. Print.

Camus, Albert, and Justin O’Brien. The Myth of Sisyphus. New York: Vintage International, 2018. Print.

“How Did Albert Camus Die?” Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc. Web. 25 June 2021.

Aronson, Ronald. “Albert Camus.” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University, 10 Apr. 2017. Web. 25 June 2021.